Saturday, June 29, 2013
Descola "All Kinds of Animals" (VIDEO)
Würzburg Summer School for Cultural and Literary Animal Studies 2012 opening keynote by Prof. Philippe Descola, from the Collège de France, Paris. Keynote delivered at the University of Würzburg, in Germany on 24 September 2012. For further details, please visit www.summerschool-clas.de
Philippe Descola is the author of "Par-delà nature et culture" ("Beyond Nature and Culture") and delivers his talk entitled "All kinds of Animals", in which he presents several possible and existant concepts for the relation between humans and animals. These are naturalism, totemism, analogism and animism, each of which are limited to specific historical and ethnological contexts.
Dewey and Descola: philosophical ecology and environmental philosophy (DOWNLOAD)
Per yesterday's post. Link HERE to a book (.pdf) that was just ahead of its time.
Friday, June 28, 2013
Descola's 'The Ecology of Others'
Thursday, June 27, 2013
quote of the day
"Do not make the mistake of thinking that one faith is safe from monsters and the other is not."
- John D. Caputo, "Cross and Khôra"
"One consequence of epistemic finitude is that we do not know the divine names of things."- Ray Brassier
(HT/Source: Theologoumena)
Wednesday, June 26, 2013
Adrian Ivakhiv's new book, 'Ecologies of the Moving Image'
Looks great, link HERE. I've known Adrian for a few years now - emailing him a few times and even sending him my own book. He's always been a pleasure to work with, has been supportive and charitable in the blogosphere. Great guy to be around. Congrats Adrian!
Monday, June 24, 2013
Laruelle "In-the-Last-Humanity: On the 'Speculative' Ecology of Man, Animal and Plant” (MP3 DOWNLOAD)
Link to MP3 HERE. From the LGS Seminars (info copied below).
Professor François Laruelle – In-the-Last-Humanity: On the “Speculative” Ecology of Man, Animal and Plant
This is the third in a series of lectures Professor François Laruelle is giving at the London Graduate School, London. This talk was presented with the support of the School of Art, Central Saint Martins, University of the Arts.
Professor Laruelle has taught at both the University of Paris X and the Collège international de philosophie, and is a Visiting Professor at the London Graduate School, Kingston University, London. He is the author of over twenty books, including Philosophies of Difference (trans. 2010), Future Christ (trans. 2010), Principles of Non-Philosophy (trans. 2013), and, most recently, The Concept of Non-Photography (2011) and Anti-Badiou (2011, trans. 2013).
Friday, June 21, 2013
quote of the day
“Atheism is a strategy of the besieged. One begins by admitting that the territory of immanence is just as religion describes it, then one declares that this territory is the only one that exists, and finally one invents every possible way of rendering it livable despite that fact.”
- Q. Meillassoux
Thursday, June 20, 2013
quote of the day
"In religion humans are strangers to themselves, because when they submit to God they do not submit to their essence but to the very opposite of their essence."
- Quentin Meillassoux
- Quentin Meillassoux
Wednesday, June 19, 2013
Robert Brandom: Reason Genealogy and the Hermeneutics of Magnanimity
Ht dmf.
Robert Brandom, Distinguished Professor of Philosophy, University of Pittsburgh, argues that genealogies (Marx, Nietzsche, Freud, Foucault) present the revenge of naturalism on rationalism. Hegel teaches us how to replace the genealogical hermeneutics of suspicion with a hermeneutics of magnanimity that allows us to see naturalism and rationalism as complementing rather than competing with one another.
Robert Brandom, Distinguished Professor of Philosophy, University of Pittsburgh, argues that genealogies (Marx, Nietzsche, Freud, Foucault) present the revenge of naturalism on rationalism. Hegel teaches us how to replace the genealogical hermeneutics of suspicion with a hermeneutics of magnanimity that allows us to see naturalism and rationalism as complementing rather than competing with one another.
Monday, June 17, 2013
Hegel's naturalism
A new book published on Hegel and naturalism (ndpr link HERE, amazon link HERE) which looks fairly interesting. I am not really a fan of how Pinkard writes - having read his Legacy of Idealism book - however the ndpr review raves about this, Pinkard's newest, so I thought to give it a try (one should ignore the weird review found on amazon, it doesn't seem legit).
Here is something astounding from the amazon blurb. Basically we are told that Pinkard pitches Hegel as an "anti-totality" thinker, as someone who dwells in the unresolvability of oppositions. To each Hegel scholar their own, but I am wondering why Pinkard goes for this specific interpretation yet so far as I can tell Schelling's philosophy, which seems to accomplish this goal already, isn't wrestled with (instead it's Aristotle, which fits considering the theme of the book is naturalism).
Second, here is a juicy introductory quote from the ndpr review:
What will differ from Pinkard's book is that the new continental naturalism will be post-intentional and refrain from superimposing an elevated sense of *human* good as a final end of life. It is true that creatures seek to free themselves from contradiction and tension and that biologically this is what (via practices, conceptual or otherwise) institutes short term teloi. Thus, I think that there *can be* "final ends" within the new continental naturalism but it will not be so traditionally conceived as Pinkard lays it out. If anything, a "final end" would simply be the end of all life - thus universal or absolute death would, on a more generalized metaphysical level, take the place of life; one may have something like "void," annihilation, death, or non-being take life's place as transcendental meontology.
Here is something astounding from the amazon blurb. Basically we are told that Pinkard pitches Hegel as an "anti-totality" thinker, as someone who dwells in the unresolvability of oppositions. To each Hegel scholar their own, but I am wondering why Pinkard goes for this specific interpretation yet so far as I can tell Schelling's philosophy, which seems to accomplish this goal already, isn't wrestled with (instead it's Aristotle, which fits considering the theme of the book is naturalism).
Second, here is a juicy introductory quote from the ndpr review:
A few posts back I mentioned the rise of continental naturalism and I truly believe that Hegel will play a major role in shaping that naturalism, as will Schelling (in a major way Schelling already has through Iain Grant's naturphilosophie), and one must add Brandom and Sellars too the range of influences at play here.In just 200 pages of text plus notes, Terry Pinkard's new book is a masterpiece of clear, scrupulous exposition and an exceptionally able defense of Hegel's thought. It is, if anything, more interesting philosophically than the outstandingly accomplished Hegel exegesis that it also is. In taking up the broad theme of culture as second nature, both metaphysically and ethico-politically, Pinkard combines the virtues of McDowell on second nature (but with more historical details and a more developed conception of history than anything on offer in McDowell), Merleau-Ponty on embodiment (but with a greater sense of the role, too, of reason in concept formation and revision, especially in ethics, than in Merleau-Ponty), and Brandom on inferential articulation (but with a greater sense of human embodiment and of the situation of the human subject in the modern world than in Brandom).
What will differ from Pinkard's book is that the new continental naturalism will be post-intentional and refrain from superimposing an elevated sense of *human* good as a final end of life. It is true that creatures seek to free themselves from contradiction and tension and that biologically this is what (via practices, conceptual or otherwise) institutes short term teloi. Thus, I think that there *can be* "final ends" within the new continental naturalism but it will not be so traditionally conceived as Pinkard lays it out. If anything, a "final end" would simply be the end of all life - thus universal or absolute death would, on a more generalized metaphysical level, take the place of life; one may have something like "void," annihilation, death, or non-being take life's place as transcendental meontology.
Sunday, June 16, 2013
the new french philosophy
A nice review essay covering Ian James' The New French Philosophy over at 3:AM, link HERE.
Saturday, June 15, 2013
continental naturalism: Sellars, Brandom, Kant, Hegel
Jon Cogburn has some interesting comments up HERE over at Newapps concerning the rise of naturalism in 21st century continental philosophy.
Jon correctly points out (in my opinion) that these influences could probably be summed up by locating the spirit of continental naturalism in German idealism, ontologically speaking. Epistemologically speaking, the more "sciencey" moments and emphasis on the *powers* of the mathematical may even come from our readings of Kant, if not from the trust put into the power of reason and of the concept, via someone like Hegel. I should note that what Hegel does with concepts, how he locates them *within* the world and thus within a natural register, is especially important for my own philosophical project of "speculative naturalism." Brassier mentioned some similar thoughts concerning what Hegel does with the concept too (I am referring to his recent talk on naturalism).
Naturalism isn't often associated with continental philosophy, and that's for a number of reasons. But neither was "realism" associated with the continental tradition. In fact, continental philosophy - so the argument goes - was "anti-realist" since its postmodern days, which are now fading. Likewise, I think that naturalism is a philosophical viewpoint that 21st century continental philosophy has yet to adopt.
One contemporary philosopher whose work I look forward to, especially when it comes to naturalism, is Adrian Johnston. I've said before that while I share Brassier's and Johnston's naturalist convictions, the major disagreement between us comes down to whether theism can play any role here. Johnston emphatically (and polemically) answers in the negative, while I have a different viewpoint.
I plan on writing something answering to his criticisms, hopefully soon. Yes, I know. Promises, promises.
Jon correctly points out (in my opinion) that these influences could probably be summed up by locating the spirit of continental naturalism in German idealism, ontologically speaking. Epistemologically speaking, the more "sciencey" moments and emphasis on the *powers* of the mathematical may even come from our readings of Kant, if not from the trust put into the power of reason and of the concept, via someone like Hegel. I should note that what Hegel does with concepts, how he locates them *within* the world and thus within a natural register, is especially important for my own philosophical project of "speculative naturalism." Brassier mentioned some similar thoughts concerning what Hegel does with the concept too (I am referring to his recent talk on naturalism).
Naturalism isn't often associated with continental philosophy, and that's for a number of reasons. But neither was "realism" associated with the continental tradition. In fact, continental philosophy - so the argument goes - was "anti-realist" since its postmodern days, which are now fading. Likewise, I think that naturalism is a philosophical viewpoint that 21st century continental philosophy has yet to adopt.
One contemporary philosopher whose work I look forward to, especially when it comes to naturalism, is Adrian Johnston. I've said before that while I share Brassier's and Johnston's naturalist convictions, the major disagreement between us comes down to whether theism can play any role here. Johnston emphatically (and polemically) answers in the negative, while I have a different viewpoint.
I plan on writing something answering to his criticisms, hopefully soon. Yes, I know. Promises, promises.
Tuesday, June 11, 2013
Monday, June 10, 2013
Society for German Idealism (CALL FOR PAPERS)
THE SOCIETY FOR GERMAN IDEALISM
Call for Papers
The Society for German Idealism will meet at the Pacific APA,
16-20 April 2014, Westin Gaslamp Quarter, San Diego.
Papers must not exceed a length of 3000 words. Include the following ten items:
(1) word count -- 3000 words maximum!
(2) author's name
(3) academic status (professor, unaffiliated, graduate student)
(4) highest earned degree (BA, MA, PhD)
(5) institutional affiliation (if any)
(6) mailing address
(7) email address
(8) telephone number
(9) the paper's title
(10) an abstract -- 100 words maximum!
Include this information in the body of your email and on the first
page of your paper.
No more than one submission by the same author will be considered.
Email a copy of your paper, as an attachment, in
Microsoft Word (.doc),
Rich Text Format (.rtf),
or Adobe Portable Document Format (.pdf)
to idealism@lclark.edu
Label your attachment as follows:
YourLastName_YourFirstName -- for example, Hegel_Georg.doc
Papers must be received by 1 SEPTEMBER.
Papers will be reviewed by a committee. Three papers will be selected
for presentation, and each paper will have a commentator.
Notification of acceptance will be made via email in October.
Submissions whose authors cannot be contacted through email will be
rejected.
If you would like to serve as a commentator, please email
idealism@lclark.edu by 1 September.
https://sites.google.com/a/lclark.edu/idealism/sgi has information
about The Society for German Idealism.
PLEASE FORWARD THIS TO ANYONE WHO WOULD BE INTERESTED.
Sunday, June 9, 2013
Thursday, June 6, 2013
postdocs available in process ontology & contemporary biology
Reposted from the University of Exeter link HERE.
A Process Ontology for Contemporary Biology
ERC Advanced Investigator Award, Grant Agreement #324186
This project has three central aims. The first is to rethink central
issues in the philosophy of biology by elaborating an ontology for
biology that takes full account of the processual nature of living
systems. Starting with a careful survey of existing positions,
especially Whitehead and the American Pragmatists, the goal will be to
develop a concept of process adequate for addressing the multiple levels
of interacting processes at different time scales characteristic of
living systems. The concept of a stable biological thing will be
analysed as a stabilised process relative to an appropriate time
scale, and this conception should make possible a better
understanding of familiar biological pluralisms (about genes, organisms,
species, etc…) in terms of different ways in which distinct scientific
practices intersect with biological processes.
Second, the concept of process developed will be used to rethink some
highly topical issues in contemporary philosophy of biology (and
philosophy of science generally). The project will explore the
potential of a processual perspective to provide a critique of widely
discussed recent versions of mechanism. The latter have been deployed to
offer accounts of explanation and, eventually, causation. Such accounts
will be assessed for the possibility of revision in the light of
modifications suggested by a processual perspective. The project will
explore generally the relevance of this perspective to influential
contemporary accounts of causation and explanation.
Finally the project will apply the preceding ideas to
several highly active and important areas of contemporary biology:
systems biology, synthetic biology, and microbiology. These
investigations, in fact, will be carried on in parallel with the more
general philosophical enquiries, with the idea that the two will be
mutually informative: the philosophical analyses will not only be
applied to scientific concepts, but will also themselves be evaluated
for their relevance to real cutting edge biology. This evaluation will
be guided by interaction with scientific practitioners and an expert
Advisory Board, as well as text-based study. The project aims to be of
direct relevance to both philosophy and science.
Some preliminary attempts to address some of these issues can be
found in J. Dupré, Processes of Life: Essays in the Philosophy of
Biology, OUP 2012, especially parts 2 and 3.
The project will employ three postdoctoral research fellows. The
first, currently recruiting, is a four year Associate Research
Fellowship. The appointee will work closely with the PI on all aspects
of the project.
To apply, please complete an application form, your CV and covering letter with the contact details of three referees to Hanan Price (H.Price@exeter.ac.uk) quoting the reference number P45222 in any correspondence.
To download the application and equal opportunities form please follow the below links;
Two further posts will be advertised during the academic year
2013-14. These will be to work specifically on the application of the
project themes to (i) systems and synthetic biology, and (ii)
microbiology. Anyone interested in any of these posts is welcome to
contact the PI at j.a.dupre@exeter.ac.uk.
Wednesday, June 5, 2013
a Meillassoux dictionary
Thanks to Peter Gratton for the offer to be a contributor to the forthcoming The Meillassoux Dictionary through EUP. I have been assigned "the divine inexistence," and surrounding concepts. This should be a fun project and I look forward to working on it.
Edinburgh University Press has a number of these dictionaries out, here is a LINK to the one on Deleuze.
Edinburgh University Press has a number of these dictionaries out, here is a LINK to the one on Deleuze.
Speculative Naturalism: A Bleak Theology in Light of the Tragic
"Speculative Naturalism: A Bleak Theology in Light of the Tragic"
Abstract
Theological perspective upon the
relationship between deity and creature may not be as radically open to a full
range of possible value as has once been thought. If one is seeking a capacious view of deity, creatures, and nature, I contend that not only should one account for
continuity, wholeness, healing, salvation, warmth, benevolence, and joy in one’s
religious metaphysics, but also for discontinuity, difference, diremption, rupture,
trauma, tragedy, melancholy, coldness, and the more “somber” tones of the
divine life. These features seem to be
just as important as any strictly positive evaluation of deity in establishing its full
range of possible value, even its "fading embers" of value that seem to continually ignite ablaze both wrath and love. My exploration
of this “darker” side of religious naturalism, a “bleak theology” as I am
calling it, begins by articulating its opposite in the axiologically positive
evaluation of nature and deity found within the “mainstream” of American religious
naturalism, especially within the 19th and 20th centuries
(including process theology). I then offer some speculative theses about the relationship
between deity and the natural world in more somber dimensions, developing my
reasoning as to why a darker side of deity ought to be accounted for, and can
be accounted for, within a perspective which I call “speculative naturalism,” a “bleak” theology.
"Darkness and occlusion make out the character of primal time. All life is at first night; it gives itself shape in the night...Thus too wrath must be earlier than love." - F.W.J. Schelling
"Darkness and occlusion make out the character of primal time. All life is at first night; it gives itself shape in the night...Thus too wrath must be earlier than love." - F.W.J. Schelling
Saturday, June 1, 2013
naturalism and the problem of spirit
“I possess a sense of divine transcendence from the Catholic tradition balanced by a pagan appreciation of the mystery of nature itself, the sensuous being-there of the world in its sometimes unbearable beauty.”
- William Desmond, from Perplexity and Ultimacy
“…every visible and invisible creature can be called a theophany, that is, a divine apparition. For…the more secretly it is understood, the closer it is seen to approach the divine brilliance. Hence the inaccessible brilliance of the celestial powers is often called by theology ‘Darkness.’”
– John Scotus Eriugena from Periphyseon
NATURALISM AND THE PROBLEM OF SPIRIT
Panel
Douglas Anderson, Southern Illinois University, Carbondale
Thomas Alexander, Southern Illinois
University, Carbondale
Randal E. Auxier, Southern Illinois
University, Carbondale
Stephen Tyman, Southern Illinois University,
Carbondale
PAPER ONE
"Natura Americana"
Doug Anderson - SIUC
Doug Anderson - SIUC
Briefly, for our discussion of
American conceptions of nature, I will sketch the nineteenth century outlooks
of Emerson and Peirce that stand in opposition to mechanistic and positivistic
accounts of nature and naturalism that came to dominate twentieth century
American culture. To see the
experiential import of the Emersonian-Peircean outlook, I will then turn to a
brief description of several suggestions made by Henry Thoreau and Henry Bugbee
regarding our relations with “nature” in its various guises.
Emerson and Peirce
The background to American
nineteenth century conceptions of nature can be found in the work of Spinoza
and Schelling. The key is that Nature
reveals itself in a variety of ways or modes, all of which are real. Schelling brings life and dynamism to
Spinoza’s nature and thus underwrites both Emerson’s organicism and Peirce’s
evolutionary cosmology. Two features shared
by their accounts of nature are important to their overall outlooks: 1) nature
is creative and remains open to possibility, and 2) nature reveals a
fundamentally tripartite categorial structure.
For Peirce this triadicity is found in his three ontological
categories—firstness, secondness, and thirdness. For Emerson, it is described in his
commitment to the idealist categories of the “I,” the “not-me,” and the
Over-Soul or synthetic Being in and through which the first two are
operative. Thus, Natura Americana is
constituted of several natures. Nature
as being or Soul is the living continuum in which natura naturans—creative,
agentive nature—engages natura naturata—the realm of commodified things
operating under the laws of Nature in an orderly fashion.
The upshot of this sketch is that
we humans are “natured’ in several ways.
As creators and experimenters, we are naturing; we will entities in our
environment to conform to our purposes and desires. As embodied beings, on the
other hand, we are akin to all other natured entities. The key here is that the so called
“emergentism” of various evolutionary outlooks takes on a radically different
meaning from that given it in the twentieth century. That animals, including humans, emerge in
nature does not indicate to Emerson and Peirce that they are merely natured
beings in a determinate set of causal relations. On the contrary, as Schelling suggested,
evolutionary emergence of these beings reveals the fundamental dynamism and
life in Nature. The consequences of this
difference are tremendous, and it is upon these that I will focus in our panel
discussion.
Curiously, mechanism, positivism,
and behaviorism are positions to which most philosophers no longer admit, or
which they argue have been redescribed sufficiently to overcome the charge of
reductionism. I am not convinced by
these claims and believe that something like these views continues to
underwrite, often tacitly, much contemporary thought.[1] In any case, I take the issue to be still
alive and perhaps even more dangerous to the extent that it is operative while
being denied. Most of us are well aware
of the consequences of the mechanist’s reductive move. Under it, animals and persons can be treated
as quantifiable behavioral events and can be effectively manipulated and
managed in this way. Such thinking has
led to the eclipse of the humanities in western culture and has reduced
solutions to human problems in many instances to technical manipulation of
causes. But what knowledge is and how it
is possible are sheer mysteries from this outlook—this is the very reason
positivism sought to eradicate philosophical thought. If one cannot answer a question, one simply
excommunicates it from the pool of legitimate questions.
The Emersonian-Peircean view of
Nature does understand the import of causal and empirical thinking because it
sees clearly the roles of natura naturata in experience; they both see a role for scientific
inquiry. As Peirce maintained, “an
idealist need not deny the reality of the external world . . . for the reality
of the external world means nothing except that real experience of duality” (CP
5.539). However, both Peirce and Emerson
wanted to know, among other things, how this understanding (call it scientific
knowledge) is possible. It is important
to note here that what is important to both of them is not that positivism, for
example, does not engage in transcendental argumentation but that reductionist
accounts are inadequate to make sense of our actual human experiences. In quite different ways they both argue that
we humans (and any other inquiring beings) represent Nature’s
self-knowing. Being like the very Nature
in and through which we emerge, we have an access to its meaning. “Nature,” Peirce argued, “only appears
intelligible so far as it appears rational, that is, so far as its processes
are seen to be like processes of thought” (CP 3.422). Thus, to understand
ourselves (and Nature) is to understand our embodied finitude but also our
abilities to conduct our own lives—to act.
Consequently, in seeing that Nature is not a dead mechanism but dynamic,
evolving Being, we see that it bears its own meaning. Peirce was adamant that his semeiotic did not
lead to a subjectivism but to an objective or conditional idealism. Nature, he argued, reveals its meaning to
us—its laws, habits, and general meanings.
Part of our human task is to learn about these in order to engage in a
conduct of life. Part of our task is also to create further meaning—this was
the key to Schelling’s defense of both science and poetry. “Genius,” Emerson believed, “is the activity
which repairs the decay of things, whether wholly or partly of a material and
finite kind” (Emerson, 330).
Thoreau, Bugbee, and
Experience
It was the richness of this
transaction between natura naturans and natura naturata that Thoreau and Henry
Bugbee attempt to get us to see in an experiential way. Thoreau’s metaphor of “walking” points to our
agency in general; we can act; we can make things happen and make them new—we
are Nature in its participial mode.
However, there is always a temptation to remain asleep to our
possibilities—to deaden ourselves. This
deadening became systematic for positivism and the generic versions of scientism
it spawned in twentieth century culture.
As Peirce noted earlier, “a man who enters into the scientific thought
of the day and has not materialistic tendencies, is getting to be an
impossibility” (CP 8.38). Thoreau
anticipated this deadening move in American thought and Bugbee found himself in
the midst of it. Despite the respect
Quine and Putnam had for Bugbee as a thinker when he was at Harvard, they knew
that an Ivy League school in the 1950-60s could not hire a philosopher who
spoke and wrote as Bugbee did. In The
Inward Morning he set up a powerful line of resistance to the reductionism that
had become our culturally habitual way of treating our natural state of being.
In treating both ourselves and
other natural entities as “things” we lose sight of meaning and of our natural
community. We hear still the claim that
the meaning, say, of a piece of land is only that which a particular person
sees in it—subjective and relative. It
is of course obscure what this subjective “meaning” is in a nominalistic world,
but even if we grant its presence, the fundamental issue goes unexplored. In order for any present feature of natura
naturata to have meaning for us, it must own that possibility itself. It exhibits its own meaning—there is, as
Spinoza and Dewey insisted, a transaction between natura naturans and natura
naturata. Thus Bugbee tries to show us
how “things” live with us in a natural community—they are gifts for us to learn
about. Their utility, as Emerson
suggested, is a part of that meaning but does not exhaust that meaning.
Finally, the upshot for both
Thoreau and Bugbee is that Nature is the wilderness within which we and the
rest of both natura naturans and natura naturata learn to live. Our conduct of life is thus a part of a much
larger organic evolution. As Emerson
suggested: “There are no fixtures in
nature. The universe is fluid and volatile” (Emerson 279). We play a role in this fluid and volatile
evolution and therefore bear some existential responsibility. Because of our finitude we must be attentive
to the otherness that surrounds us. At
the same time, our agency is what creates new possibilities, so we must remain
“wild” or “alive” or “awake” in order to ongoingly re-civilize the world. We, as natural agents, are in league with
nature as “natured” in generating the creative development of Nature. To be egoistic in this endeavor is one of the
consequences of the twentieth century positivistic conception of nature—we come
to act only for ourselves, as if we had ontological priority and
independence. Thoreau and Bugbee, in
concert with the systematic efforts of Emerson and Peirce, point to the dangers
and limitations inherent in this consequence, and they offer another, richer
perspective on the very meaning of our natural lives.
PAPER TWO
"Ecological Naturalism and the
Aesthetics of Spirit"
Thomas Alexander - SIUC
Thomas Alexander - SIUC
Nature has been a central theme in
American philosophy; “naturalism” may be said to be to thematize nature as an
inclusive interpretive principle. Not only will the determination of “the
nature of nature” be ultimate in such an approach, but it will have
consequences for the possibilities for the meaning of human existence. Let us
call the ways in which human existence experiences such meanings of the world
and itself an “aesthetics” or life of spirit. Insofar as an aesthetics of
spirit seeks to provide a “home” of meaning for human existence, one question
for any version of naturalism will be what sort of “home” it provides, what
sort of “ecology” of existence it makes possible.[2] I will undertake to
schematize four types of naturalism and their implications for an ecology of
spirit: scientific naturalism, humanistic naturalism, ontological naturalism,
and transcendental naturalism. While each type represents a genuine existential
possibility that may be chosen without the others, I will argue that each may
be appropriated as a domain of an inclusive naturalism, which I call
“ecological naturalism.”
Scientific naturalism is the most
familiar version, so that it is often regarded as determinative of the meaning
of “naturalism” altogether. Nature is understood entirely as the object of
scientific inquiry, and is contrasted with the “supernatural.” Nature itself is
generally portrayed reductively; consequently, knowledge is limited to
scientific methodology, and human consciousness is correspondingly transformed
into an analytical knowing-machine (e.g. Quine, Wilfrid Sellars, Dennett). Such
a position leaves the “aesthetics of spirit” the options of either fulfilling
itself completely in the life of science or seeking other values in a
supernatural realm (e.g. Pascal). One other option is evidenced by the later philosophy
of Santayana. A committed materialist, Santayana portrayed a rich concept of
“the realm of spirit” that achieved fulfillment in the intuition of essences.
Though both spirit and essence for him originated in the realm of matter, they
were inherently unconcerned with their origins and, considered in themselves,
were impersonal and ahistorical, occupying a “poetic” dimension of being. This
option aside, philosophy considered within the framework of scientific
naturalism is fundamentally epistemology and adjacent fields like philosophy of
mind. An ecological naturalism would accept nature as an object of knowledge,
though not exclusively such, just as it would accept as aspects of a life of
spirit the pursuit of natural knowledge or the aesthetic intuitionism of a
“realm of spirit” without limiting it to those. Indeed, both nature as a field
of knowledge and as an immanent possibility for aesthetic appreciation are
highly significant ways of inhabiting nature.
Humanistic naturalism takes nature
primarily as a “world,” the vital context of human life, which involves far
more than the search for knowledge or the mastery of nature. The world is not a
mere universe of knowable objects, but the “place” or “scene” of the drama of
human existence. This is Dewey’s presentation of nature as “experience.”
Experience is not Quine’s “surface stimulation of sense organs” but intelligent
action. Culture is the way in which nature is thus engaged: it is hunted,
farmed, molded into bricks, worshipped.[3] Here the meaning of nature is
determined by the view, “nature is what nature does.” This applies to its most complex
manifestations even more than to its most elementary ones. For Dewey the
aesthetic and religious experiences are most revelatory of the possibilities of
nature. Nature is such that new forms “emerge” over time. The life of spirit
here is the aesthetics of cultural existence—the creation of meanings and
values expressive of a way of life. And philosophy here is philosophical
anthropology: inquiry into symbol, semiosis, and the theory of civilization. An
ecological naturalism would certainly be concerned with understanding how human
experience and culture inhabit the world and civilize it as a major aspect of
the ecology of spirit.
But understanding nature
emergentistically remains problematic, so that the question of the being of
nature as such must be raised. Ontological naturalism begins with the conscious
search to clarify a more complex understanding of nature than just a broadly
defined field of human activity. This requires a systematic undertaking, such
as we find in Justus Buchler’s “ordinal naturalism.”[4] Nature as an object of
philosophical reflection is engaged as phusis—the manifestation of beings in
time. It must be articulated by categorical complexity to reflect its order and
diversity and by a polymodal ontology to reflect its temporality and process;
e.g., modes of actuality and possibility, plurality and integrity, and others
must be used. Modes and categories must express the inclusive being of nature
as a “manifestation.” (For example, see Buchler’s appropriation of the natura
naturans/natura naturata distinction.[5]
Another example would be an ecological ontology, or “eco-ontology,” that
articulates a view of the being of nature in terms of inter-relation, process,
complexity, order, etc. and that would be conducive to an ecological approach
to knowledge, ethics, aesthetics, etc.) Ontological naturalism takes nature
here as the object of theoretical contemplation, and the life of spirit is
manifested in the forms of “logos” and “theoria,” discursive contemplation at a
high level of generality, adequacy, and integrity for the end of an integrative
understanding of nature itself as a ground of existence. Philosophy here is
metaphysics: contemplative comprehension.
Speculation originates with awe and
wonder, and this moves us to the fourth mode of naturalism, transcendental
naturalism. As humanistic naturalism was more inclusive than the concern for
empirical knowledge, so transcendental naturalism includes more approaches to
nature than that of theoretical understanding. Nature is the locus of human
existence confronting itself and the mystery of being as such; awareness of
mystery is what makes approaching nature possible at this level at all. Nature
is experienced as a showing-forth or epiphany of the sacred or holy. There are
various ways in which mystery is encountered. Nature exhibits a number of
“faces” or personae to human existence other than those available to Logos
(which discerns nature in the Apollonian faces of luminosity, order, and
speech). There are also: depth, chaos, creation, destruction, persistence,
transience, beauty, horror, love, hate, silence. The faces or masks are
archetypal and have often been symbolized as the “gods” of various religions.
But insofar as the acknowledgement of the sacred springs from deep within,
inner aspects of the self are also realized. Instead of Logos, the speech that
pertains to this dimension is Mythos.[6] Though religions are profuse with
symbol and rituals to embody or enact these meanings, there may also be a
transcendence of symbol in mysticism.
This is “naturalism” in the name
of the nature that includes more than reflective reason and yet which is
capable of being richly symbolized and participated in. Human existence
comports itself toward nature through these personae, which have a profoundly
determinative meaning on how life is lived. Such an encounter is an immanent
possibility for human existence. When undergone, the transcendence of the
ordinary world and the ordinary self for deep nature and the deep self involves
transformation, metamorphosis. The result for the aesthetics of spirit is
sacred existence. Emerson may stand to represent this form of naturalism in the
American tradition. Nature for him became the discipline whereby spirit came to
itself and transformatively and actively reoriented itself to the world. This
is where the “axis of vision” would be restored.[7] The spiritual aesthetics of
transcendental naturalism involve realizing the deepest values creatively in
existence and experiencing the world with “morning wisdom”—a state of awakened
insight.[8] Philosophy conducted here is transcendental. An ecological
naturalism would be transcendental in regarding nature as evocative of awe, as
an epiphany for awareness of the sacred, and a fundamental existential opening
of the self at levels beyond reason.
I conclude with the thesis that
these four ways of understanding nature and its possibilities for spirit are
each legitimate options on their own, but also present the question as to
whether they can be integrated into an inclusive “naturalism.” I present
ecological naturalism as such a position. The basic human desire is the desire
to experience the world with meaning and value, which may be termed the Human
Eros. The extent to which nature can be encountered as a home (oikos) for Eros
orients us to the world in terms of creative love and care. While this Eros may
be satisfied with utterly nonnatural homes, to the extent that we are alive to
the need to care for nature—as we must in the civilization to come—we will need
an aesthetics of spirit that finds itself at home in nature so that it may care
for it.
PAPER THREE
“Imagination, Spirit, and Symbol in Emerson’s
Nature”
Randy Auxier - SIUC
Randy Auxier - SIUC
In spite of much scholarly
attention over the years, the structure of the “argument” in Emerson’s
Nature(1836) is poorly understood. I argue that to follow its movements
properly, one must grasp the way Emerson combines the theories of Spirit from
German Naturphilosophie with a logic of imagination that has its roots in Kant,
Coleridge, Goethe, Hegel, Schelling, and Vico. A structural analysis of the
argument in Nature will reveal its debts to these sources while casting light
upon how the argument actually proceeds.
Specifically, I argue that the
central chapters of Nature, chs. 3-8, each recapitulate the same imaginative
territory as the earlier ones, but under an ever deepening sense of the
symbolic functions of nature itself, demonstrating a series of organically
connected significations at each level. Each level is increasingly “free,” and
each level indicates its own mode of freedom. All levels point to one and the same
truth of Spirit, discoverable finally in what Emerson calls “the sentiment of
virtue.”
Hence, for example, where
“Economy” symbolizes the sentiment of virtue in the mode of daily exigency,
need, and the mundane, nevertheless, the movement of Spirit and the sentiment
of virtue are discoverable in the course of getting a living and the choices
such activities present, because such activities are not wholly driven by
exigency but are also symbolic of something basic in our constitution. Freedom
is discoverable providence (the providing for daily need) in the cycles of
everyday life. It is possible to imagine activities driven by need and mundane
society under their symbolic heads, and to find the workings of Spirit within
them.
Similarly, “Beauty” reveals a mode of
freedom at the level of the senses and the way in which “forms” are available
to the sensitive body, natural, spiritual and intellectual forms all bespeak an
integral order grasped in the sign of light or illumination. This illumination
is the mode of bodily freedom and reaches deeper than freedom in the economic
mode. The other chapters follow a similar path in deepening the sense of
freedom. The path Emerson follows in the descent into the layers of symbolism
is an adaptation of Coleridge, and to some extent Vico and Goethe.
My analysis, therefore, follows
the path of Spirit through its varying symbolic modes of freedom to reach the
“sentiment of virtue,” set out in the key chapter on “Discipline” in the form
of what I call Emerson’s “grand analogy.” Here we see that sensible objects are
apprehended in both the mode of matter and of mind, and that their material
existence is appropriated by “understanding” while their spiritual meaning is
appropriated by “reason.” When understanding and reason are brought under the
same discipline of form, the analogy appears in which the categories of
understanding, space and time, find their meaning in the “sentiment of virtue,”
which is the way in which reason appropriates “law” in the universe. The
analogy of the categories and the sentiment of virtue brings common sense (the
mode of understanding) into analogy with religion (the mode of reason, and
teaches both body and spirit the moral law. The philosophical account of
understanding and reason in these chapters, and its culmination in the grand
analogy which teaches the moral law, is Emerson’s adaptation and synthesis of
the Kantian philosophy.
The moral law is tempered by
perspective and is ascended to by the will to power. At this point
transcendence becomes possible for finite persons, and “Idealism,” in Emerson’s
sense, is the integrated philosophical assessment of the modes of transcendence
under the headings of nature, poetry, philosophy, science, and religious
ethics. The idealistic philosophy is a human hypothesis which creates a
framework for an account of spirit, or the relation of God to the creation and
sustaining of the world of nature. The journey of spirit through these various
forms of freedom is Emerson’s adaptation of Hegel’s and Schelling’s
philosophies.
My essay concludes with an
assessment of our prospects in light of Emerson’s vision of the relation of
nature and spirit.
PAPER FOUR
"Nature, Spirit and Desire"
Steve Tyman - SIUC
Steve Tyman - SIUC
The work of bringing closer
together or putting on a common footing the disparate camps gathered around the
themes of nature and spirit, while vital at this time, must not ignore the
genuine impediments that lie in the way of the enterprise. To be sure, the
enterprise itself is at present nothing less than a cultural imperative. One
need only reflect upon the utter dysfunctionality of current debates such as
the evolution/intelligent design fiasco to understand that the argument on both
sides is falsely framed, with the result being that the confrontation produces
much heat but little light. The argument adumbrated here will go to the
suggestion that the two concepts are entirely coordinate, that they are locked
in a binary relationship as tightly interwoven as that between the north and
south poles of a magnet. But having said this, it is still incumbent upon us to
discern a certain functional dissonance, even as it were a dimensional
fracture, which distinctively characterizes the problem as we must at present
encounter it. This means in effect that the two dimensions of spirit, on the
one hand, and nature, on the other, do after all tend to fall apart from one
another, with the result being that real work of a very practical kind remains
to be done to bring them back into a vital and functioning relationship.
By practical work I still mean
something of the order marked out by Kant when, as part of his comprehensive
attempt to take the measure of the meaning of Aufklarung, he distinguished this
from theoretical work, and proceeded to mark out as discrete the associated
realms of free will and nature. The distinction between the two domains of
discourse is as radical here as it is in any vector of Western thought. It is
radical to the point of entailing two entirely diverse and even antithetical
sets of presuppositions. While theory, thus understood, is predicated on the
universal applicability of such concepts as causation to anything that can be
encountered under the rubric of phenomenon – that is, anything that can be
experienced –, practice in its essential possibility is predicated on the
capacity, on the part one who proposes to act, freely, in fact, to do so. It is
in the element and atmosphere of this essential freedom that all free
undertakings are conceived and generated; and it is here, too, of course, that
moral judgements concerning the value of individual acts are registered. Now
the connundrum that Kant himself faced in relation to his original inability to
conceive free action, action attributable to legislative reason, as anything
but already moral, given that it represents by definition, the application of
self-generated moral law, need not detain us here. For this consequence, we
find, is the result of that central facet of Kant’s approach that I regard as
flaw and foible. This flaw is evident already in the Kantian concept of nature.
Nature as it is here understood coincides with the scope and range of possible
experience, or what may be brought before the mind as something understood. It
was by limiting nature to this meaning, and segregating this from the reach of
moral meaning, that Kant was able, as he thought, to have his cake (his natural
science) and eat it, too, that is, also to preserve the humanly all-important
sense of moral activity.
What is wanting in this account, in
my estimation, is something the lack of which is due to the extreme limitation
Kant placed – for clear strategic purposes, no doubt – on his concept of
experience. Notably, Kant did not allow for direct experience by the self of
the self. On the one hand, from a theoretical point of view, this opened up the
corridor of investigation invested in the function of critique, and, beyond the
scope of what Kant himself envisioned, made thinkable the mediated problematics
of situating the unmanifest self as diverse as those of Marx, Freud, and
Foucault. From an immediate practical/personal point of view, however, the
vista was not so encouraging. With respect to the self, the distinction between
freedom and nature runs right through the middle of the house. It is easy to
see why the tradition of pragmatism, prefigured as I understand, already by
Fichte and his school, was resolved to move into this middle zone and to speak
of an essential and irreducible inter-engagement of self and world. While there
is, for many purposes, substantial merit to be found in this orientation, it
seems to me that the correlated emphasis on situated enactability mostly leaves
out of account a dimension especially in need of investigation. That is the
dimension of what, in one capacity, is recognized as will, and, in another
capacity, is recognized as desire.
The task is to think these two
capacities as two dimensions of one reality. If this project is thinkable, Kant
cannot have been right to think desire simply as that part of nature that
reaches, willy nilly, into the human constitution, and there will simply be
what it will be, such that moral action is generated largely in despite of this
condition. Instead, we will need to find a way to own desire and to take responsibility
for it even up to the absolute. But merely to proclaim this as desideratum is
not to establish its viability; much less is it to accomplish the task itself.
Indeed, in order to make a beginning here, one does well to take not as a given
fact but as a problem the Kantian position that desire is really not tractible
in the sense of simply being subject to human volition. The recalcitrance and
hidden nature of the origins of desire, fugitive animal that it is, is
precisely the point of embarkment. The remainder of my reflections go to
address this issue. In the course of this address, a conception of what I will
call spiritual evolution will be developed.
[1] See, for example, the curious
case of Rorty’s “physicalism.”
[2] By “ecology” is meant a concern with interactive, dynamic systems
that support a variety of “homes” (oikoi) for beings-in-relation. Interaction
and development (like evolution and natural history) are fundamental ways of
understanding the being of nature.
[3] “‘Experience’ denotes the
planted field, the sowed seeds, the reaped harvests, the changes of night and
day…that are observed, feared and longed for; it also denotes the one who
plants and reaps, who works, rejoices, hopes, fears, plans, invokes magic or
chemistry to aid him…” (LW 1:18).
[4] See Justus Buchler, The
Metaphysics of Natural Complexes (1966; 2nd ed. 1990).
[5] See Justus Buchler, The
Metaphysics of Natural Complexes, Ch. III and “Probing the Idea of Nature,”
Process Studies Vol 8, No. 8 (1978), included in the second edition of MNC. The
distinction has a complex and not very consistent history ranging from Eriugena
to Aquinas to Bruno to Spinoza to Schelling to Buchler. See Olga Weijers,
“Contribution à l’histoire des termes ‘natura naturans’ et natura naturata’
jusqu’ à Spinoza,” Vivarium XVI, 1 (1978), pp. 70-80.
[6] By “mythos” I mean an account
that reveals and constitutes a fundamental identity in human existence or the
world, and for that reason is treated as very important or sacred. See Mircea
Eliade’s term hierophany.
[7] Emerson, Nature, Ch.
VIII, “The axis of our vision is not coincident with things, and so they appear
not as transparent but opake. The reason why the world lacks unity, and lies
broken and in heaps, is because man is disunited with himself. He cannot be a
naturalist, until he satisfies all the demands of the spirit. Love is as much
its demand, as perception. Indeed, neither can be perfect without the other. In
the uttermost meaning of the words, thought is devout, and devotion is thought.
Deep calls unto deep. But in actual life, the marriage is not celebrated. There
are innocent men who worship God after the tradition of their fathers, but
their sense of duty has not yet extended to the use of all their faculties. And
there are patient naturalists, but they freeze the subject under the wintry
light of the understanding. Is not prayer also a study of truth—a sally of the
soul into the unfound infinite? No man ever prayed heartily, without learning
something. But when a faithful thinker, resolute to detach every object from
personal relations, and see it in the light of thought, shall at the same time
kindle science with the fire of the holiest affections, then will God go forth
anew into the creation.”
[8] See Ibid. where he contrasts
the cognitio vespertina (evening knowledge) of man with the cognitio matutina
(morning knowledge) of God. See also Thoreau, Walden, Ch. 2.
Subscribe to:
Posts (Atom)